Generic Freeness and Chevalley’s Theorem I

This post and the next is my work on Exercises 7.4 A-7.4.O of section 7.4 in Vakil’s note. We discuss Chevalley’s Theorem and prove it using Grothendieck’s Generic Freeness Lemma.

We first discuss some properties of constructible sets and then we prove Grothendieck’s generic freeness lemma following a sequence of exercises in Vakil’s notes.  Then we use Generic Freeness to prove Chevalley’s Theorem. Though there are more direct ways to prove it, such as the proof we did in Thursday’s lecture (06/02/2020) in Applied Scheme Theory (proof of Theorem 2.2.9 in Algebraic Geometry II by Mumford and Oda). We only use Generic Freeness here as we will use it again in the future for generic flatness. Note that except proposition 1.2 the rests of the first section on the properties of constructible sets are not needed later.

We will discuss some applications of Chevalley’s Theorem including its implication of Hilbert’s Nullstellensatz in the next post: Generic Freeness and Chevalley’s Theorem II (Applications). I divided the post into two parts since the next part about applications is to be continued. The pdf file below contains the full article so far. Later more will be added into the next post.

Note that except proposition 1.2 the rests of the first section on the properties of constructible sets are not needed later.

View the full article as pdf here: Generic Freeness and Chevalley’s Theorem[16/02/2020]

chevalley's1chevalley's2chevalley's3chevalley's4chevalley's5chevalley's6chevalley's7chevalley's8

chevalley's9

As we remarked that the proof of Lemma 1.1 applied to the case that M_{i+1}/M_{i} projective is the induction step of the proof of a generalised result. We include this result here. It’s not related to another part of the post so I add it as an appendix.

The reference for this proof is the lecture notes for the course Ring Theory at Warwick, 2018: Ring Theory Lecture notes 2018.

appendix_1appendix_2

 

 

Topos as A Model for Set Theory and Independence Proof

Introduction

Part 1:  For any elementary topos, its internal logic, considered as propositional calculus, is a Heyting algebra. Some constructions are required to make a topos a suitable model of set theory, where the propositional calculus needs to be Boolean and two-valued.  We discuss some properties of topos desired for a suitable model: the existence of a natural number object (NNO), being Boolean, satisfying the axiom of choice (AC) and well-pointedness. I gave some proofs for some exercises in [1] and organise them into a thread.

Part 2: We sketch the construction of a Cohen topos, which is Boolean and satisfies the axiom of choice, where the continuum hypothesis (CH) fails [1, pp. 277-290]. After that, we improve the result by a filter-quotient construction for obtaining a well-pointed topos satisfying AC with an NNO, where CH fails. Such a filter-quotient construction indeed provides a stronger model than the Cohen topos, with the four properties mentioned above satisfied.

Full Article

Here is the article Topos as A Model for Set Theory and Independence Proof which is an excerpt from my previous work (2018) [2]. It discusses some desired properties of topos as a suitable model of set theory and ideas on the independence proof of the axiom of choice. I gave detailed proofs for some exercises in [1] and organise them into a thread. I have also cited necessary definitions and propositions for completeness (I omitted the proofs for propositions that can be directly found in [1]). Assuming basic familiarity with category theory,  this article should be self-contained.  Here is an appendix for quick reference: Appendix.

Note: there are some missing cross-references which should not affect reading.

Summary

To show the foundation aspects of topos, we have clarified the differences and connections between external and internal concepts and discussed the properties required for a topos as a suitable model of set theory, that is, the existence of a natural number object (NNO), being Boolean, satisfying the axiom of choice (AC) and well-pointedness.

The universality of the NNO was discussed and we showed how the recursion, addition, multiplication and the partial order can be defined from the NNO and how they correspond to that for sets. The propositional calculus, the Heyting algebra and some equivalent conditions for a topos being Boolean were discussed. The presheaf topos and sheaf topos, as special examples, were illustrated for the Heyting algebras and the equivalent conditions for being Boolean. Some propositions about external and internal projective objects were proved and related to the external and internal axiom of choice (AC and IAC). We proved the equivalent conditions for a presheaf topos satisfying AC or IAC, thus had an example of a presheaf topos satisfying IAC but not AC.
We also proved the equivalence of AC and IAC for a well-pointed topos and some equivalent conditions for well-pointedness.

To show an application of the foundation aspect of topos, we sketched the process of construction of the Cohen topos, which is Boolean and satisfies AC, where the continuum hypothesis (CH) fails, with some details examined. We then proved that the filter-quotient construction on the Cohen topos preserves the cardinal inequality and the NNO. We also proved that the filter-quotient topos constructed from a Boolean topos satisfying AC is well-pointed and again satisfies AC. Together with the fact that a well-pointed topos is both Boolean and two-valued, we concluded that the filter-quotient topos constructed from the Cohen topos satisfies all the properties for sets and violates CH, thus is an improved model in the independence proof.

Further Remark

Later in the book [1], the Mitchell-Benabou language, as a first-order language for topos, is constructed, and then the relation to set theory will become clear. The internal properties we have discussed can be expressed by some formulas that correspond to the formulas expressing related properties in set theory. For example, a topos is Boolean iff the formula  \forall p( p\vee \neg p)  holds; a topos satisfies IAC iff the formula for AC holds. Also, the geometric construction for the independence proof can be translated to the language of forcing. On the other hand, we can say that the symbols in logic can be interpreted diagrammatically through categories. In this way, we see the symbolic and diagrammatic aspects of logic. Topos theory provides a diagrammatic view of logic, which is particularly good when dealing with structures. Though the idea in the independence proof is actually equivalent to that in set theory, the diagrammatic view and by topos theory gives us a different viewpoint.

References

[1] MacLane, S., & Moerdijk, I. (2012). Sheaves in geometry and logic: A first introduction to topos theory. Springer Science & Business Media.

[2] Likun Xie. (2018). Topos Foundation for Set Theory. Unpublished Bachelor Thesis. The University of Manchester, UK.

Categorical Construction of Fibre Product of Schemes

Following our discussion of glueing schemes: Categorical descriptions for glueing sheaves and schemes. We now discuss the construction of the fibre product of schemes by glueing.

Given arbitrary schemes X,Y,S, let q:X\to S and r: Y\to S be the given morphisms. Let \{S_i\} be an open affine cover of S. Let X_i=q^{-1}(S_i), Y_i=r^{-1}(S_i), choose an affine open cover X_{ij} for X_i and an affine open cover Y_{jk} for Y_k. The fibre product is constructed by glueing various X_i\times_{S_i} Y_i  together.

We rewrite the glueing construction of fibre product in a more categorical way as follows. Note that the colimit here is glueing construction and the consequences of the two pullback squares should be clear thinking in terms of schemes.

View as pdf: Construction of fibre product

Theorem[Thm 3.3, [1]/ Thm 9.1.1, [2]] For any two schemes X and Y over a scheme S, the fibre product X\times _S Y exists and is unique up to unique isomorphism.

construction1construction2

reference

Variations of Yoneda Lemma; Monos, Epis and Isomorphisms of (Pre)sheaves

The first part is my work on a variation of Yoneda Lemma. The second part is my work on Exercises 2.4A, 2.4.C-2.4.D of section 2.4 in Vakil’s notes.

1.  Variations of Yoneda Lemmas (Monos, Epis and Isomorphisms of Presheaves)

Here are a few variations of Yoneda Lemma I played around a few years ago, which bear similar ideas of Yoneda Lemma. Recently I have been dealing with sheaves again, so I just reviewed some old stuff here. I used these variations to show that a morphism of presheaves is monic resp. epic if and only if it’s injective resp. surjective on the level of sections (For another proof see here https://stacks.math.columbia.edu/tag/00V5).

Here are the variations and proofs for presheaves: (pdf version: Variations of Yoneda lemma)

variation0yoneda2yoneda3yoneda4

 

2.  Monos, Epis and Isomorphisms of Sheaves 

Here we give a detailed discussion for sheaves, following exercises in Section 2.4 of Vakil’s notes: (pdf version: Monos, epis and isomorphisms of sheaves)mono0

mono2mono3mono4mono5mono6mono7

Categorical descriptions for glueing sheaves and schemes

In this post, we give a categorical proof of Lemma 33.2 (Tag 00AK) by showing that a glued sheaf is defined as an equaliser. This equaliser provides a tool for calculating global sections of glued schemes. We later present some examples for calculating global sections and glueing constructions using (co)limits descriptions. (Sometimes people say they may lose insights about the details and the real maths behind abstraction. But it really depends on one’s approach and ways of thinking. ) The goal of this post is to give a structured summary of glueing constructions of schemes after meditating on explicit constructions, using categorical language. It is not meant to replace explicit arguments for schemes, but to give some ideas on how general a construction is and whether it can be transferred to a different setting. For example, we will know what to do if we are working on a site with a different Grothendieck topology instead of the Zariski topology. Note that some consequences of the categorical facts we use are indeed straightforward for schemes, for example, the two pullback squares in Example 4. This post is open-ended and more examples of glueing will be added. 


Remark. Note that for a sheaf \mathcal {F} on a topological space and an open cover U=\bigcup U_i,

\displaystyle \mathcal {F}(U) =\mathrm{lim}_J \mathcal{F}(U_i),

where J is the covering sieve generated by the covering \{U_i\}, namely, J is the collection of all those V\subset U with V\subset U_i for some i. This limit is equivalent to the following equaliser diagram in the usual sheaf definition:

equaliser

where for t\in FU, e(t)=\{t|_{U_i} \mid i\in I\} and for a family t_i\in FU_i, p\{t_i\}=\{t_i| _{U_i\cap U_j}\},  q\{t_i\}=\{t_j| _{U_i\cap U_j}\}.

For a scheme X=\bigcup X_i with an open cover \{X_i\} in the Zariski topology, X is the colimit indexed over the covering sieve generated by the covering \{X_i\}. This colimit can also be simplified to be a coequaliser diagram.


First, we include the explicit constructions for glueing sheaves and some sources for details check of these constructions. The categorical proof we are going to show is a categorical rephrasing by meditating on these constructions, which gives a more structured presentation.

Glueing Morphisms

Proposition A.1  [Tag 00AK] Let X be a topological space. Let X=\cup U_i be an open covering. Let \mathcal{F},\mathcal{G} be sheaves of sets on X. Given a collection

\phi_i:\mathcal{F}|_{U_i}\to \mathcal {G}|_{U_i}

of maps of sheaves such that for all i,j\in I the maps \phi_i,\phi_j restrict to the same map \mathcal {F}_{U_i\cap U_j}\to \mathcal{G}_{U_i\cap U_j}, then there exists a unique map of sheaves

\phi: \mathcal {F}\to \mathcal{G}

whose restriction to  each U_i agrees with \phi_i.

Proof. Take any s\in \mathcal{F}(V), where V\subset X is open, and let V_i=U_i\cap V. Then we have an element \phi_i (s| _{V_i})\in \mathcal{F}(V_i) and \phi_i (s| _{V_{ij}})=\phi_j (s| _{V_{ij}}) by the glueing condition. Thus by the sheaf condition for G, the sections \phi_i(s|_{V_i})\in G(V_i) patch together to give a section in G(V), define this section to be \phi(s). (We omitted the checking details. )                                                   \square

Glueing Sheaves

Explicit construction of glueing sheaves is given in Lemma 6.33.2, Tag 00AK, but the details of checking have been omitted.  For some details of a reality check,  see this post.

glueing dataglueing morphism

Proof of Lemma 6.33.2: (Pdf version: Proof of sheaf glueing)

glueing sheavesglueing sheaves2

Glueing Schemes

To glue schemes, one needs to define the glued topological spaces which will be a quotient space of the disjoint union of the glued spaces and then verify the structure sheaves of the glued schemes satisfy the condition of Lemma 6.33.2 [see Tag 01JA].

Example 1. (The affine line with doubled origin is not affine).   Let k be a field. Let X= \text{Spec} (k[t]), Y= \text{Spec}(k[u]). Let U=D(t) =\text{Spec}k[t,1/t]\subset X \text{ and } V= D(u)=\text{Spec}k[u,1/u]\subset Y.  Consider the ismorphism U\cong V given by t\leftrightarrow u.  Let Z be the glued scheme, from the equaliser diagram in the proof of Lemma 6.33.2,  we see that the structure sheaf \mathcal{O}_Z is given by

\mathcal{O}_{Z}(W) = \mathcal{O}_X(W \cap X) \times_{\mathcal{O}_{X(W \cap X \cap Y)} \cong \mathcal{O}_{Y}(W \cap X \cap Y)} \mathcal{O}_Y(W \cap Y).

Thus the global section \mathcal{O}_Z(Z) \text{ is } k[t] \times_{k[t,t^{-1}] \cong k[u,u^{-1}]} k[u] \cong k[t]. From this we see that Z is not affine, since  Z=\text{Spec}(k[t]) which is not the case: the underlying topological space Z has one more point- the doubled origin.


Added on 21/01/2020

Example 2. (Quasiseparated scheme is glued from affine schemes). Note that every scheme is a colimit of affine schemes. This is true in general by the fact that every sheaf is a colimit of representables and that the Zariski topology is subcanonical (see here for more details).

For the case that a scheme X is separated (for which the intersection
of any two affine open sets is affine), take an affine open cover \bigcup U_i=X such that each intersection U_{ij} is affine, then X is just the coequaliser of the diagram \coprod_{i,j} U_{ij} \rightrightarrows \coprod_{i} U_i. This is the glueing construction as we described above.

If X is not separated, one can still write X as a colimit of affines but not with the same diagram as we used for glueing, see here for a description of the diagram.

Remark. One implication of viewing X as a colimit is: let Sch and Rings be the categories of schemes and rings respectively, given that \text{Hom}_{\textbf{Rings}}(A,B)\cong \text{Hom}_{\textbf{Sch}}(\text{spec}(B),\text{spec}(A)), one can deduce that for any scheme X\text{Hom}_{\textbf{Rings}}(R,\Gamma(X,\mathcal{O}_x))\cong \text{Hom}_{\textbf{Sch}}(X,\text{spec}(R)) by the fact Hom-functor preserves (co)limits.


Added on 01/02/2020

Example 3 (Proj construction). [Section 4.5.7, Vakil]

Let S_\bullet=\oplus _{n\in \mathbb{Z}} S_n be a \mathbb{Z}-graded ring and S_+=\oplus_{i>0} S_i be the irrevalant ideal. Suppose f\in S_+  is homogeneous, there is a bijection between the prime ideals of ((S_\bullet)_f)_0 and the homogeneous prime ideal of (S_\bullet)_f. The projective distinguished open set D(f)= \mathrm{Proj} S_\bullet \setminus V(f) is identified with \mathrm{Spec}((S_\bullet)_{f})_0. If f,g\in S_{+} are homogeneous and nonzero, D(f)\cap D(g)= \mathrm{Spec} ((S_\bullet)_{fg})_0) is isomorphic to the distinguished open subset D(g^{\mathrm{deg} f}/f^{\mathrm{deg}g}) of \mathrm{Spec} ((S_\bullet)_f)_0, similarly for \mathrm{Spec} ((S_\bullet)_g)_0. \mathrm{Proj}S_\bullet is glued from various \mathrm{Spec}((S_\bullet)_{f})_0 along the pairwise intersections \mathrm{Spec}((S_\bullet)_{fg})_0.

Example 4. (Fibre product of schemes)[For detailes of a categorical proof of this construction, see the post: Construction of Fibre Product of Schemes or the pdf here: Construction of fibre product.]

Given arbitrary schemes X,Y,S, let q:X\to S and r: Y\to S be the given morphisms. Let \{S_i\} be an open affine cover of S. Let X_i=q^{-1}(S_i), Y_i=r^{-1}(S_i), choose an affine open cover X_{ij} for X_i and an affine open cover Y_{jk} for Y_k. The fibre product is constructed by glueing various X_i\times_{S_i} Y_i  together.

 

 

Notes and Remarks on Unstable Motivic Homotopy Theory

I have made some notes and remarks about motivic homotopy theory while working on my master dissertation during the summer of 2019.

Affine representability results: 

For remarks on section 2.3 and Lemma 2.3.2 of [2] (also quoted as Proposition 5.5 and Proposition 5.6 in [1]), we take the approach of stack and descent.  By relating hyperdescent condition for simplicial presheaves with descent for stacks [3], we show that how this implies classifying space of a stack satisfies hyperdescent.

After that, we give a different proof and some remarks of Lemma 2.3.2 based on my understanding, see Proposition 0.0.2 and Proposition 0.0.3 in Stack and descent.

Exercises on the construction of motivic homotopy theory: 

I also have some informal notes about the exercises in [1]. The following are some of my proofs for the exercises, in the remarks, I also pointed out some typos I found which may be helpful for other readers: Exercises on A Primer.

 

 

[1] Antieau, B., & Elmanto, E. (2017). A primer for unstable motivic homotopy theory. Surveys on recent developments in algebraic geometry95, 305-370.

[2] Asok, A., Hoyois, M., & Wendt, M. (2018). Affine representability results in 𝔸1–homotopy theory, II: Principal bundles and homogeneous spaces. Geometry & Topology22(2), 1181-1225.

[3] Jardine, J. F. (2015). Local homotopy theory. Springer.